Political
Philosophy and the Future
Isaiah Berlin asked, why philosophy? He answered, ÒThe
goal of philosophy isÉto assist men to understand themselves and thus operate
in the open, and not wildly, in the dark.Ó 1 As U.S. society becomes
increasingly diverse and faces increasingly complicated problems of foreign
policy, economics and climate change, a discussion of modern political theory
is useful. This academic field now deals with how to handle substantive
political disagreements, rather than determining how to live in harmony with a
fundamental human nature, however defined.
An example of this is an essay, What Is Political Philosophy? by
Brown professor Charles Larmore, who
presents a recursive argument that we restate. People who agree to do
things a certain way constitute a society. This is articulated by the idea of
justice that defines the shape of social life as a whole. But people also
disagree. 2 There then arise problems of conflict and power that
politics is meant to solve. Politics, therefore
differs from the individual ethic of morality because politics is not fact free.
It is directly embedded in the history of a people and the real problems
they have encountered as a society along the way, so they may live together.
U.S. law, a product of both precedent and present politics, is an example of
this.
Almost all Americans agree that they have individual
rights that preserve their freedoms and that, in the Enlightenment tradition, they deserve a hearing by others who will respect
them. Where Americans disagree is on the scope of their freedoms. According to
Yuval Levin, the conservative author of The
Great Debate (2014), Ò(Thomas) Paine expressly disagrees with (Edmund)
Burke 's notion that charities can take care of the poor....Poverty,
it seems, is taken by Paine to be one of those coercive realities that constrain
people's freedom, from which the state ought to protect people, so as to allow
their will and choice free rein." 3 The results of Paine's
assumption have been government programs that ameliorate and modify the volatile markets.
In The Great Debate,
Levin thoroughly discusses the ideological differences between these two men;
which, amazingly enough, are the same as the differences between the
Democrats and Republicans in the 21st century. We then ask how these
differences matter.
Thomas Paine was born in 1737 in Thetford, England. His
father was a pacifist Quaker and his mother an Anglican As a result, ÒHe had a
lifelong ingrained sense that the laws of justice are clear and simpleÉÓ 4
He was introduced to Benjamin Franklin, who impressed with PaineÕs intelligence
and drive, advised him to seek a new start in America. After working for a
Philadelphia publisher, he became the magazineÕs editor and, with the 1775
publication of his pamphlet, Common Sense
became the voice of the American Revolution. He argued:
1) England
was beset with the dual tyrannies of monarchy and aristocracy,
that made no sense. More naturally, a system of frequent elections
ensured the fidelity of legislators to the public interest.
2) America
was comprised of peoples from all of Europe; but by its dependence upon Great
Britain, it was unnecessarily involved in European quarrels.
3) Furthermore,
Britain misruled the colonies for her own benefit and did not consider their
best interests. A historical note: After the Glorious Revolution of 1688, the
British began to create the modern state and continued to reform its system of
public finance and taxation, in order to better wage war on the continent. 5
A majority of the colonies had before elected their own governors. London then
began to appoint its American governors from the British ruling class; then
parliament imposed direct taxation by the Stamp Act. 6 Needless to
say, the colonists did not feel represented.
On the issue of independence, a majority of the American
colonists were Òon the fence.Ó The Wikipedia states, Common Sense tipped the balance. 7 After its
publication, they rose in outright revolution.
A crucial assumption of PaineÕs political thought was his
assumption that moral ethics existed separate from the social context, as a
scientific law differs from engineering. For him, there were two main political
principles:
ÒThomas PaineÕs model of natureÉoffered both means and
ends for political action by holding up a particular understanding of nature
– taken to be a set of rational rules that began from individualism
and equality - as the standard of legitimacy that could give shape to change
over time.Ó 8 From these two principles, the rational rules by
which all societies should be governed could be derived as from scientific law.
PaineÕs Enlightenment thought greatly influenced the
Revolution; but he was kept away from the Constitutional Convention of 1787
because he denounced the bicameral approach to government, supported universal
suffrage and an end to slavery. 9 The resulting U.S. Constitution of
1787 was a set of compromises, that history would
later revise in a better form.
What about Edmund Burke? He was born in Dublin, Ireland
likely in 1729. His father was a prominent Protestant and his mother a
Catholic. Born into a society with religious divisions, he saw the positive
side where, ÒThe experience of seeing differences in dogma made moot in
practice by the bonds of family affection and neighborly respect was formative
for him. It seemed to leave him with a lasting sense that life was more
complicated in practice than in theory – and that this was a good thingÉ.He retained a sense of how accommodations built up slowly
from reserves of trust, warm sentiment, and moderation could enable people to
live together even in the face of social tension, political oppression, and
economic plight.Ó 10 Writing to prevent the contagion of the British
Isles from the French Revolution, his political philosophy can best be summed
up by a quote from Reflections on the
Revolution in France (1790), ÒA state without the means of some change, is without the means
of its own
preservation.Ó 11 Politics to Burke always dealt with the particular
and, ÒHe is concerned that an
overreliance on theory may unleash extremism and immoderation by unmooring
politics from the polity.Ó 12
Although
BurkeÕs prescription for moderate social adaption was well-founded
in most cases, it suffers from the defect that, by rejecting reason and by
relying excessively upon the past, it does not respond well to large and abrupt
changes. Some challenges are immediate and pressing, and society must act
decisively (and correctly). An incremental philosophy cannot deal well with
abrupt changes: such as an Hitler (note the lack of an
isolationist response), a large market crash (note the lack of decisive
government action in the early 1930s and CongressÕ grudging response to 2008),
or impending climate change.
After
our discussion about the philosophies which animate
the political left and the right, where does this leave
us? Are Paine and Burke relevant in the 21st century? We could ask,
what would they say about the problems that confront the U.S.? Paine would say, start
with the goal. Edmund Burke would say, rely on (local) politics to come up with
the solution. In the 21st century both views matter when
circumstances such as advancing technology, sustained turmoil abroad, changing
economic patterns 13 and climate begin to matter a lot. These,
short-term market transactions address only partially or not at all. Put even
more simply, in a consensual democratic society, Paine specifies the goals; and
Burke specifies the means.
The
following are useful frames of mind for problem solving, which requires social
trust rather than simply an aimless maneuvering for power. In Ò5 Minds for the
Future, (2008) Ó Howard Gardner, Harvard professor of Cognition and Education
writes:
ÒÉI
concern myself here with the kinds of minds that people will need if they
– if we - are to thrive in the
world during the eras to comeÉ
The disciplined mind has mastered at least one
way of thinking – a distinctive mode of cognition that characterizes a
specific scholarly discipline, craft, or professionÉ
The
synthesizing mind takes information
from disparate sources, understands and evaluates that information objectively,
and puts it together in ways that make sense to the synthesizer and also to
other persons.
Building
on discipline and synthesis, the creating
mind breaks new ground. It puts forth new ideas poses unfamiliar questions,
conjures up fresh ways of thinking, arrives at unexpected answersÉthe creating
mind seeks to remain at least one step ahead of even the most sophisticated
computers and robots.
Éthe respectful mind notes and welcomes
differences between human individuals and between human groups, tries to
understand these Òothers,Ó and seeks to work effectively with them. In a word
where we are all interlinked, intolerance or disrespect is no longer a viable
option.
Éthe ethical mind ponders the nature of
oneÕs work and the needs and desires of the society in which one lives.Ó 14